The Completeness of Scientific Theories - On the Derivation of Empirical Indicators within a Theoretical Framework: The Case of Physical Geometry (Paperback, Softcover reprint of the original 1st ed. 1994)


Earlier in this century, many philosophers of science (for example, Rudolf Carnap) drew a fairly sharp distinction between theory and observation, between theoretical terms like 'mass' and 'electron', and observation terms like 'measures three meters in length' and 'is _2 Degrees Celsius'. By simply looking at our instruments we can ascertain what numbers our measurements yield. Creatures like mass are different: we determine mass by calculation; we never directly observe a mass. Nor an electron: this term is introduced in order to explain what we observe. This (once standard) distinction between theory and observation was eventually found to be wanting. First, if the distinction holds, it is difficult to see what can characterize the relationship between theory :md observation. How can theoretical terms explain that which is itself in no way theorized? The second point leads out of the first: are not the instruments that provide us with observational material themselves creatures of theory? Is it really possible to have an observation language that is entirely barren of theory? The theory-Iadenness of observation languages is now an accept ed feature of the logic of science. Many regard such dependence of observation on theory as a virtue. If our instruments of observation do not derive their meaning from theories, whence comes that meaning? Surely - in science - we have nothing else but theories to tell us what to try to observe.

R4,555

Or split into 4x interest-free payments of 25% on orders over R50
Learn more

Discovery Miles45550
Mobicred@R427pm x 12* Mobicred Info
Free Delivery
Delivery AdviceShips in 10 - 15 working days



Product Description

Earlier in this century, many philosophers of science (for example, Rudolf Carnap) drew a fairly sharp distinction between theory and observation, between theoretical terms like 'mass' and 'electron', and observation terms like 'measures three meters in length' and 'is _2 Degrees Celsius'. By simply looking at our instruments we can ascertain what numbers our measurements yield. Creatures like mass are different: we determine mass by calculation; we never directly observe a mass. Nor an electron: this term is introduced in order to explain what we observe. This (once standard) distinction between theory and observation was eventually found to be wanting. First, if the distinction holds, it is difficult to see what can characterize the relationship between theory :md observation. How can theoretical terms explain that which is itself in no way theorized? The second point leads out of the first: are not the instruments that provide us with observational material themselves creatures of theory? Is it really possible to have an observation language that is entirely barren of theory? The theory-Iadenness of observation languages is now an accept ed feature of the logic of science. Many regard such dependence of observation on theory as a virtue. If our instruments of observation do not derive their meaning from theories, whence comes that meaning? Surely - in science - we have nothing else but theories to tell us what to try to observe.

Customer Reviews

No reviews or ratings yet - be the first to create one!

Product Details

General

Imprint

Springer

Country of origin

Netherlands

Series

The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, 53

Release date

December 2013

Availability

Expected to ship within 10 - 15 working days

First published

1994

Authors

Dimensions

229 x 152 x 16mm (L x W x T)

Format

Paperback

Pages

278

Edition

Softcover reprint of the original 1st ed. 1994

ISBN-13

978-9401043939

Barcode

9789401043939

Categories

LSN

9401043930



Trending On Loot